The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762-1814)


Johann Gottlieb Fichte is one of the major figures in German philosophy in the period between Kant and Hegel. Initially considered one of Kant's most talented followers, Fichte developed his own system of transcendental idealism, the Wissenschaftslehre, which sought to work out in great detail Kant's insight that finite rational beings such as ourselves are to be interpreted in terms of both theoretical and practical reason. Through technical philosophical works and popular writings Fichte exercised great influence over his contemporaries, especially during his years at the University of Jena. His influence waned towards the end of his life, and Hegel's subsequent dominance in German philosophy relegated Fichte to the status of a transitional figure whose thought helped to explain the development of German idealism from Kant's Critical philosophy to Hegel's philosophy of Spirit. Today, however, Fichte is rightly seen as an important philosopher in his own right, as a thinker who carried on the Kantian legacy of transcendental philosophy in a highly original form.

Table of Contents (Clicking on the links below will take you to that part of this article)


Fichte's Beginnings (1762-1794)

(a) Early life

Fichte was born on May 19, 1762 to a family of ribbon makers. Early in life he impressed everyone with his great intelligence, but his parents were too poor to pay for his schooling. Through the patronage of a local nobleman, he was able to attend the Pforta school, which prepared students for a university education, and then the universities of Jena and Leipzig. Unfortunately, little is known about this period of Fichte's life, but we do know that he intended to obtain a degree in theology, and that he had to break off his studies for financial reasons around 1784, without obtaining a degree of any sort. Several years of earning his living as an itinerant tutor ensued, during which time he met his future wife, Johanna Rahn, while living in Zurich.

In the summer of 1790, while living in Leipzig and once again in financial distress, Fichte agreed to tutor a university student in the Kantian philosophy, about which he knew very little at the time. His immersion in Kant's writings, according to his own testimony, revolutionized his thinking and changed his life, turning him away from a deterministic view of the world at odds with human freedom towards the doctrines of the Critical philosophy and its reconciliation of freedom and determinism.


Back to Table of Contents

(b) Fichte's sudden rise to prominence

More wandering and frustration followed. Fichte decided to travel to Königsberg to meet Kant himself, and on July 4, 1791 the disciple had his first interview with the master. Unfortunately for Fichte, things did not go well, and Kant was not especially impressed by his visitor. In order to prove his expertise in the Critical philosophy, Fichte quickly composed a manuscript on the relation of the Critical philosophy to the question of divine revelation, an issue that Kant had yet to consider. This time, Kant was justifiably impressed by the results and arranged for his own publisher to bring out the work, which appeared in 1792 under the title An Attempt at a Critique of all Revelation.

In this fledgling effort Fichte adhered to many of Kant's claims about religion by extending them to concept of revelation. In particular, he took over Kant's idea that all religious belief must ultimately withstand critical scrutiny if it is to make a legitimate claim on us. For Fichte, any alleged revelation of God's activity in the world must pass a moral test: namely, no immoral command or action, i.e., nothing that violates the moral law, can be attributed to Him. Although Fichte himself did not explicitly criticize Christianity by appealing to this test, such a restriction on the content of a possible revelation, if consistently imposed, would overturn most aspects of orthodox Christian belief: including, for example, the doctrine of original sin, which states that everyone is born guilty as a result of Adam and Eve's disobedience in the Garden of Eden. This piece of Christian theology, which is said to be grounded in the revelations contained in the Bible, is hardly compatible with the ordinary view of justice that Kant and Fichte took to be underwritten by the moral law, and that maintains that we are not guilty for crimes or transgressions that we did not commit. Attentive readers should have instantly gleaned Fichte's radical views from the placid Kantian prose.

For reasons that are still mysterious, Fichte's name and preface were omitted from the first edition of An Attempt at a Critique of all Revelation, and thus the book, which displayed an extensive and subtle appreciation of Kant's thought, was taken to be the work of Kant himself. Once it became known that Fichte was the author, he instantly became a philosophical figure of importance; no one whose work had been mistaken for Kant's, however briefly, could be rightfully denied fame and celebrity in the German philosophical world.

Fichte continued working as a tutor while attempting to reformulate his philosophical insights of recent years into his own system. He also anonymously published two political works, "Reclamation of the Freedom of Thought from the Princes of Europe, Who Have Oppressed It Until Now" and Contribution to the Rectification of the Public's Judgment of the French Revolution. It became widely known that he was their author; and so from the very beginning of his public career, he was identified with radical causes and views. In October 1793 he married his fiancee, and shortly thereafter unexpectedly received a call from the University of Jena to take over the chair in philosophy that Karl Leonhard Reinhold (1758-1823), a well-known exponent and interpreter of the Kantian philosophy, had recently vacated. Fichte arrived in Jena in May 1794.


Back to Table of Contents

The Jena Period (1794-1799)

(a) Fichte's philosophical vocation

In his years at Jena, which lasted until 1799, Fichte published the works that established his lasting reputation as one of the major figures in the German philosophical tradition. Fichte never exclusively saw himself as an academic philosopher addressing the typical audience of fellow philosophers, university colleagues, and students. Instead, he considered himself a scholar with a wider role to play beyond the confines of academia, a view eloquently expressed in "Some Lectures Concerning the Scholar's Vocation," which were delivered to an overflowing lecture hall shortly after his much anticipated arrival in Jena. One of the tasks of philosophy, according to these lectures, is to offer rational guidance towards the ends that are most appropriate for a free and harmonious society. The particular role of the scholar – that is, of individuals such as Fichte himself, regardless of their particular academic discipline – is to be a teacher of mankind and a superintendent of its never-ending progress towards perfection.

Throughout his career Fichte alternated between composing philosophical works for scholars and students of philosophy and popular works for the general public. This desire to communicate to the wider public – to bridge the gap, so to speak, between theory and praxis – inspired his writings from the start. In fact, Fichte's passion for the education of society as a whole should be seen as a necessary consequence of his philosophical system, which continues the Kantian tradition of placing philosophy in the service of enlightenment, the eventual liberation of mankind from its self-imposed immaturity, i.e., its willing refusal to think for itself, and thus its responsibility for failing to act independently of the guidance of external authority.


Back to Table of Contents

(b) Fichte's system, the Wissenschaftslehre

Fichte called his philosophical system the Wissenschaftslehre. The usual English translations of this term as "science of knowledge," "doctrine of science," or "theory of science" can be misleading, since today these phrases carry connotations that can be excessively theoretical or too reminiscent of the natural sciences. Therefore, many English-language commentators and translators prefer to use the German term as the untranslated proper name that designates Fichte' s system as a whole. Another source of confusion is that Fichte's book from 1794/5, Foundations of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre, is sometimes simply referred to as the Wissenschaftslehre. Strictly speaking, this is incorrect, since this work, as its title indicates, was meant as the foundations of the system as a whole; the other parts of the system were to be written later. Much of Fichte's work in the remainder of the Jena period attempted to complete the system as it was envisioned in the Foundations of 1794/5.


Back to Table of Contents

(c) Background to the Wissenschaftslehre

Before moving to Jena, and while he was living in the house of his father-in-law in Zurich, Fichte wrote two short works that presaged much of the Wissenschaftslehre that he devoted the rest of his life to developing. The first of these was a review of a skeptical critique of Kantian philosophy in general and Reinhold's so-called Elementarphilosophie ("The Philosophy of Elements") in particular. The work under review, an anonymously published polemic called Aenesidemus, which was later discovered to have been written by Gottlob Ernst Schulze (1761-1833), and which appeared in 1792, greatly influenced Fichte, causing him to revise many of his views, but without leading him to abandon Reinhold's concept of philosophy as rigorous science, an interpretation of the nature of philosophy that demanded that philosophical principles be systematically deduced from a single, foundational principle known with apodictic certainty.

Reinhold had argued that this first principle was what he called the "principle of consciousness," namely, the proposition that "in consciousness representation is distinguished through the subject from both object and subject and is related to both." From this principle Reinhold attempted to deduce the contents of Kant's Critical philosophy. He claimed that the principle of consciousness was a reflectively known fact of consciousness, and argued that it could lend credence to various Kantian views, including the distinction between the faculties of sensibility and understanding and the existence of things in themselves. Schulze countered along Humean lines by offering skeptical objections against the legitimacy of Kant's (and thus Reinhold's) concept of the thing in itself (construed as the causal origin of our representations) and by arguing that the principle of consciousness was neither a fundamental principle (since it was subject to the laws of logic, in that it had to be free of contradiction) nor one known with apodictic certainty (since it originated in merely empirical reflection on the contents of consciousness, which reflection Schulze, following David Hume, persuasively argued could not yield a principle grounded on indubitable evidence).

Fichte, to his consternation, found himself in agreement with much of Schulze's critique. Although he was still eager to support the Kantian system, Fichte, as a result of reading Schulze, came to the conclusion that the Critical philosophy needed new foundations. Yet the search for new foundations, in Fichte's mind, was never equivalent to a repudiation of the Kantian philosophy: as Fichte would frequently claim, he remained true to the spirit, if not the letter, of Kant's thought. His review of Schulze's Aenesidemus provides one tantalizing hint about how he would subsequently attempt to remain within the spirit of Kant's thought while attempting to reconstruct it from the ground up: philosophy, he says, must begin with a first principle, as Reinhold maintained, but not with one that expresses a mere fact, a Tatsache; instead, it must begin with a fact/act, a Tathandlung, that is not known empirically, but rather with self-evident certainty. The meaning and purpose of this new first principle would not become clear to his readers until the publication of the Foundations of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre in 1794/5.

In addition to his review of the Schulze book, and still prior to his arrival in Jena, Fichte sketched out the nature and methodology of the Wissenschaftslehre in an essay entitled "Concerning the Concept of the Wissenschaftslehre," which was intended to prepare his expectant audience for his classes and lectures. Here Fichte sets out his conception of philosophy as the science of science, i.e., as Wissenschaftslehre. The Wissenschaftslehre is devoted to establishing the foundation of individual sciences such as geometry, whose first principle is said to be the task of limiting space in accordance with a rule. Thus the Wissenschaftslehre seeks to justify the cognitive task of the science of geometry, i.e., its systematic efforts at spatial construction in the form of theorems validly deduced from axioms known with self-evident certainty. The Wissenschaftslehre, which itself is a science in need of a first principle, is said to be grounded on the Tathandlung first mentioned in the Aenesidemus review. The precise nature of this fact/act, from which the Wissenschaftslehre is supposed to begin, is much debated, even today. Yet it is the essential core of the Jena Wissenschaftslehre in general, and of the Foundations of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre from 1794/5 in particular.


Back to Table of Contents

(d) Foundations of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre 1794/5

In the Foundations Fichte expresses the content of the Tathandlung in its most general form as "the I simply posits itself." Fichte is suggesting that the self, which he typically refers to as "the I," is not merely a static thing with fixed properties, but rather a self-producing process; yet if it is a self-producing process, then it must be free, since in some as yet unspecified fashion it owes its existence to nothing but itself. This admittedly obscure starting point is subject to much scrutiny and qualification as the Wissenschaftslehre proceeds. In more modern language, and as a first approximation of its meaning, we can understand the Tathandlung as expressing the concept of a rational agent that constantly interprets itself in light of standards that it imposes on itself, in both the theoretical and practical realms, in its efforts to determine what it ought to believe and how it ought to act. (Fichte's indebtedness to the Kantian notion of autonomy in the form of self-imposed lawfulness should be obvious to anyone familiar with the Critical philosophy.)

Given the difficulty of the notion, unfortunately, Fichte's Tathandlung has perplexed his readers from its first appearance. The principle of the self-positing I was initially interpreted along the lines of Berkeley's idealism, and thus as claiming that the world as a whole was somehow the product of an infinite mind. This interpretation is surely mistaken, even if one can occasionally find passages that seem to support it. More important, though, is the question of the epistemic status of the principle. Is it known with the self-evident certainty that Fichte, following Reinhold, claims must ground any attempt at systematic knowledge? And how does it serve as a basis for deducing the rest of the Wissenschaftslehre?

Fichte's method is usually said to be phenomenological, restricting itself to what we can discover by means of reflection. Yet Fichte does not claim that we simply find the fully formed Tathandlung residing somewhere in our self-consciousness; instead, we construct it in order to explain ourselves to ourselves, to render intelligible to ourselves our normative nature as finite rational agents. Thus the requisite reflection is not empirical but transcendental, i.e., a postulate adopted for philosophical purposes. That is, the principle is presupposed as true in order to account for the conditions for the possibility of our ordinary experience. Such a procedure leaves open the possibility of an alternative account of our experience, which Fichte claims can take only one form. Either, he says, we can begin (as he does) with the I as the ground of all possible experience, or we can begin with the thing in itself outside of our experience. This dilemma, as he puts it, is the choice between idealism and dogmatism. The former is transcendental philosophy; the latter, a naturalistic approach to experience that explains it solely in causal terms. The choice between the two, as Fichte famously said in the first introduction to the Wissenschaftslehre from 1797, depends on the kind of person one is, since they are mutually exclusive yet equally possible approaches.

If such a choice between starting points is possible, however, then the principle of the self-positing I lacks the self-evident certainty that Fichte attributed to it in his earlier essay on the concept of the Wissenschaftslehre. There are, in fact, those who do not find it at all self-evident, namely, the dogmatists. Fichte clearly thinks that they are mistaken in their dogmatism, yet he offers no direct refutation of their position, claiming only that they cannot demonstrate what they hope to demonstrate, namely, that the ground of all experience lies solely in objects existing independently of the I. The dogmatist position, Fichte implies, ignores the normative aspects of our experience, e.g., warranted and unwarranted belief, correct and incorrect action, and thus attempts to account for our experience entirely in terms of our causal interaction with the world around us. Presumably, however, someone who begins with a disavowal of normativity, as the dogmatists do (since that is the kind of person they are), can never be brought to agree with the idealists. There is thus an argumentative impasse between the two camps.

Fichte's remarks about systematic form and certainty in "Concerning the Concept of the Wissenschaftslehre" give the impression that he intends to demonstrate the entirety of the Wissenschaftslehre from the principle of the self-positing I through a chain of logical inferences that merely set out the implications of the initial principle in such a way that the certainty of the first principle is transferred to the claims inferred from it. (The method of Spinoza's Ethics comes to mind, but this time with only a single premise from which to begin the proofs.) Yet this hardly seems to be Fichte's true method, since he constantly introduces new concepts that cannot be plausibly interpreted as the logical consequences of the previous ones. In other words, the deductions in the Foundations of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre are more than merely analytical explications of the consequences of the original premise. Instead, they both articulate and refine the initial principle of the self-positing I in accordance with the demands made on the idealist who is attempting to clarify the nature of the self-positing I by means of reflection.

Once Fichte postulates the self-positing I as the explanatory ground of all experience, he begins to complicate the web of concepts required to make sense of this initial postulate, thereby carrying out the aforementioned construction of the self-positing I. The I posits itself insofar as it is aware of itself, not only as an object but also as a subject, and finds itself subject to normative constraints in both the theoretical and practical realms, e.g., that it must be free of contradiction and that there must be adequate reasons for what it believes and does. Furthermore, the I posits itself as free, since these constraints are ones that it imposes on itself. Next, by means of further reflection, the I discovers a difference between "representations accompanied by a feeling of necessity" and "representations accompanied by a feeling a freedom" – that is, a difference between representations of what purports to be an objective world existing apart from our representations of it and representations that are merely the product of our own mental activity. To recognize this distinction in our representations, however, is to posit a distinction between the I and the not-I, i.e., the self and whatever exists independently of it. In other words, the I posits itself as limited by something other than itself, even though it also initially posits itself as free.

The nature of this limitation is made increasingly more complex through further acts of reflection. First, the I posits a check, an Anstoß, on its practical activity, in that it encounters resistance to its will when it acts in the world. This check is then developed into more refined forms of limitation: sensations, intuitions, and concepts, all united in the experience of the things of the natural world, i.e., the spatio-temporal realm ruled by causal laws. Moreover, this world is found to contain other finite rational beings. They too are free yet limited, and the recognition of their freedom places further constraints on our activity. In this way the I posits the moral law and restricts its treatment of others to actions that are consistent with respect for their freedom. Thus, by the end of Fichte's deductions, the I posits itself as free yet limited by natural necessity and the moral law: its freedom becomes an infinite task in which it seeks to make the world around itself entirely compliant with its will, but only by doing so in an appropriately moral fashion that allows other free beings to do the same for themselves.


Back to Table of Contents

(e) Working out the Wissenschaftslehre and the end of the Jena period

Fichte's writings during the rest of the Jena period sought to fill out and refine the entire system. The Foundations of Natural Right Based on the Wissenschaftslehre (1796/7) and The System of Ethical Theory Based on the Wissenschaftslehre (1798) concern themselves with political philosophy and moral philosophy, respectively. The task of the former work is to characterize the legitimate constraints that can be placed on individual freedom in order to produce a community of maximally free individuals who simultaneously respect the freedom of others. The task of the latter work is to characterize the specific duties of rational agents who freely produce objects and actions in the pursuit of their goals. These duties follow from our general obligation to determine ourselves freely, i.e., from the categorical imperative.

Besides filling out projected portions of the system, Fichte also began to revise the foundations themselves. Since he considered the mode of presentation of the Foundations of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre unsatisfactory, he began drawing up a new version in his lectures, which were given three times between 1796 and 1799, but which he never managed to publish during his lifetime. These lectures, which in many respects are superior to the Foundations of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre, were published posthumously and are now known as the Wissenschaftslehre nova methodo.

Prior to publishing any systematic presentation of his philosophy of religion, Fichte became embroiled in what is now known as the Atheismusstreit, the atheism controversy. In an essay from 1798 entitled "On the Basis of Our Belief in a Divine Governance of the World" Fichte argued that religious belief could be legitimate only insofar as it arose from properly moral considerations – a view clearly indebted to his book on revelation from 1792. Furthermore, he claimed that God has no existence apart from the moral world order. (This second view was also an old one, initially suggested in the Aenesidemus review.) Neither view was orthodox at the time, and so Fichte was accused of atheism and ultimately forced to leave Jena.

Two open letters, both from 1799 and written by philosophers whom Fichte fervently admired, compounded his troubles. First, Kant disavowed the Wissenschaftslehre for mistakenly having tried to infer substantive philosophical knowledge from logic alone. Such an inference, he claimed, was impossible, since logic abstracted from the content of knowledge and thus could not produce a new object of knowledge. Second, Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi accused the Wissenschaftslehre of nihilism: that is, of producing reality out of mere mental representations, and thus in effect from nothingness. Whether or not these criticisms were just (and Fichte certainly denied that they were), they further damaged Fichte's philosophical reputation.


Back to Table of Contents

The Berlin Period (1800-1814)

(a) The eclipse of Fichte's career

In 1800 Fichte settled in Berlin and continued his work through private lectures and publishing new works, since on his arrival there was no university in the city. The Berlin years, while productive, represent a decline in Fichte's fortunes, since he never regained the degree of influence among philosophers that he had enjoyed during the Jena years, although he remained a popular author among non-philosophers. His first publication was a popular presentation of the Wissenschaftslehre designed to answer his critics on the question of atheism. Known as The Vocation of Man, it appeared in 1800 and is probably Fichte's greatest literary production. (It seems, though this is never explicitly stated anywhere in the book, that much of it was inspired by the personally stinging critique of Jacobi's open letter.)

Fichte continued to revise the Wissenschaftslehre, yet he published very little from these renewed efforts to perfect his system, primarily for fear of being misunderstood as he had been during the Jena years. His reluctance to publish gave his contemporaries the false impression that Fichte was more or less finished as an original philosopher. Except for a cryptic outline that appeared in 1810, his Berlin lectures on the Wissenschaftslehre, of which there are numerous versions, only appeared posthumously. In these manuscripts Fichte typically speaks of the absolute and its appearances, i.e., a philosophically suitable stand-in for a more traditional notion of God and the community of finite rational beings whose existence is grounded in the absolute. As a result, Fichte is sometimes said to have taken a religious turn in the Berlin period.


Back to Table of Contents

(b) Popular writings from the Berlin period

In 1806 Fichte published two lecture series that were well-received by his contemporary audience. The first, The Characteristics of the Present Age, employs the Wissenschaftslehre for the purposes of the philosophy of history. According to Fichte, there are five stages of history in which the human race progresses from the rule of instinct to the rule of reason. The present age, he says, is the third age, an epoch of liberation from instinct and external authority, out of which humanity will ultimately progress until it makes itself and the world it inhabits into a fully self-conscious representative of the life of reason. The second, The Way Towards the Blessed Life, which is sometimes said to be a mystical work, treats of morality and religion in a popular format.

Another famous series of lectures, Addresses to the German Nation, given in 1808 during the French occupation, was intended as a continuation of The Characteristics of the Present Age, but exclusively for a German audience. Here Fichte envisions a new form of national education that would enable the German nation, not yet in existence, to reach the fifth and final age outlined in the earlier lecture series. Once again, Fichte demonstrated his interest in larger matters, and in a manner perfectly consistent with his earlier insistence from the Jena period that the scholar has a cultural role to play.


Back to Table of Contents

(c) Fichte's return to the university and his final years

When the newly founded Prussian university in Berlin opened in 1810, Fichte was made the head of the philosophy faculty; and in 1811 he was elected the first rector of the university. He continued his philosophical work until the very end of his life, lecturing on the Wissenschaftslehre and writing on political philosophy and other subjects. When the War of Liberation broke out in 1813, Fichte canceled his lectures and joined the militia. His wife Johanna, who was serving as a volunteer nurse in a military hospital, contracted a life-threatening fever. She recovered, but Fichte succumbed to the same infection. He died of his illness on January 29, 1814.


Back to Table of Contents

Conclusion

Although Fichte's importance for the history of German philosophy is undisputed, the nature of his legacy is still very much debated. He has sometimes been seen as a mere transitional figure between Kant and Hegel, as little more than a philosophical stepping stone along Spirit's path to absolute knowledge. This understanding of Fichte was encouraged by Hegel himself, and no doubt for self-serving reasons. Nowadays, however, Fichte is studied more and more for his own sake, in particular for his theory of subjectivity, i.e., the theory of the self-positing I, which is rightly seen as a sophisticated elaboration of Kant's claim that finite rational agents must interpret themselves in both theoretical and practical terms. The level of detail that Fichte provides on these matters far exceeds that found in Kant's writings. This fact alone would make Fichte's work worthy of our attention. Yet perhaps the most persuasive testament to Fichte's greatness as a philosopher is to be found in his relentless willingness to begin again, to start the Wissenschaftslehre anew, and never to rest content with any prior formulation of his thought. Although this leaves his readers perpetually dissatisfied and desirous of a definitive statement of his views, Fichte, true to his publically declared vocation, makes them into better philosophers through his own example of restless striving for the truth.


Back to Table of Contents


Suggestions for Further Reading

Fichte's Writings in German

Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, ed. R. Lauth, H. Jacobs, and H. Gliwitzky, Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann, 1964-.

Fichtes Werke, ed. Immanuel Hermann Fichte, 11 vols., Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co., 1971. (Reprint of the 19th century edition of Fichte's work edited by his son.)

Fichte's Writings in English Translation

(Publication dates during Fichte's lifetime are given in brackets.)

Fichte: Early Philosophical Writings [1790-1799], trans. and ed. Daniel Breazeale, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1988. (Includes "Review of Aenesidemus," "Concerning the Concept of the Wissenschaftslehre," and "Some Lectures Concerning the Scholar's Vocation.")

Attempt at a Critique of all Revelation [17921, 17932], trans. Garrett Green, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978.

"Reclamation of the Freedom of Thought from the Princes of Europe, Who Have Oppressed It Until Now" [1793], trans. Thomas E. Wartenberg, in James Schmidt (ed.) What is Enlightenment? Eighteenth-Century Answers and Twentieth-Century Questions, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1996.

"On the Spirit and the Letter in Philosophy" [1794], trans. Elizabeth Rubenstein, in David Simpson (ed.) German Aesthetic and Literary Criticism: Kant, Fichte, Schelling, Schopenhauer, Hegel, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984.

The Science of Knowledge [1794/5], trans. Peter Heath and John Lachs, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982. (German title would be better translated as Foundations of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre. Also includes the two introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre from 1797.)

"On the Linguistic Capacity and the Origin of Language" [1795], in Jere Paul Surber (trans. & ed.) Language and German Idealism: Fichte's Linguistic Philosophy, Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1996.

Foundations of Transcendental Philosophy (Wissenschaftslehre) nova methodo (1796/99), trans. and ed. Daniel Breazeale, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1992. (Posthumously published lectures given between 1796 and 1799.)

The Science of Rights [1796/7], trans. A E. Kroeger, London: Trübner & Co., 1889. (Reprint — London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1970.) (German title would be better translated as Foundations of Natural Right Based on the Wissenschaftslehre. An unreliable translation.)

Introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre and Other Writings [1797-1800], trans. and ed. Daniel Breazeale, Indianapolis: Hackett Pub. Co., 1994. (Includes the two introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre from 1797 and "On the Basis of Our Belief in a Divine Governance of the World" from 1798.)

The Science of Ethics as Based on the Science of Knowledge [1798], trans. A E. Kroeger, London: Kegan Paul, 1897. (German title would be better translated as The System of Ethical Theory Based on the Wissenschaftslehre. An unreliable translation.)

The Vocation of Man [1800], trans. Peter Preuss, Indianapolis: Hackett Pub. Co., 1987.

"A Crystal Clear Report to the General Public Concerning the Actual Essence of the Newest Philosophy: An Attempt to Force the Reader to Understand" [1801], trans. John Botterman and William Rasch, in Ernst Behler (ed.) Philosophy of German Idealism, New York: Continuum, 1987.

The Popular Works of Johann Gottlieb Fichte, trans. W. Smith, 2 vols., London: Chapman, 1848/9. (Reprint — London: Thoemmes Press, 1999.) (Includes The Characteristics of the Present Age and The Way Towards the Blessed Life, both from 1806.)

Addresses to the German Nation [1808], trans. R. F. Jones and G. H. Turnbull, Chicago: Open Court, 1922. (Reprint — Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, Inc., 1979.)

"The Science of Knowledge in its General Outline" [1810], trans. Walter E. Wright, Idealistic Studies 6 (1976): 106-117.

Other Philosophers' Writings in English Translation

George di Giovanni and H. S. Harris (trans. and ed.), Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post-Kantian Idealism, Albany: State University of New York Press, 1985. (Includes excerpts from Reinhold's The Foundation of Philosophical Knowledge and Schulze's Aenesidemus.)

Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi, The Main Philosophical Writings and the Novel Allwill, trans. George di Giovanni, Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press, 1994. (Includes Jacobi to Fichte.)

Suggested Secondary Literature in English, French, and German

Daniel Breazeale, "Fichte and Schelling: The Jena Period," in Robert C. Solomon and Kathleen M. Higgins (eds.), The Age of German Idealism (Routledge History of Philosophy, Volume VI), London: Routledge, 1993. (See pp. 142-160 for Fichte's Jena Wissenschaftslehre.)

Daniel Breazeale, "Fichte, Johann Gottlieb" in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol. 3, London: Routledge, 1998.

Dieter Henrich, "Fichte's Original Insight," trans. David Lachterman, Contemporary German Philosophy 1 (1982): 15-53. (Influential article that interprets Fichte as moving beyond a reflective theory of consciousness.)

Wilhelm G. Jacobs, Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Reinbek bei Hamburg: Rowohlt, 1984. (Illustrated biography, written in German.)

Wayne Martin, Idealism and Objectivity: Understanding Fichte's Jena Project, Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1997.

Frederick Neuhouser, Fichte's Theory of Subjectivity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.

Alexis Philonenko, L'oevre de Fichte, Paris: Libraire Philosophique J. Vrin, 1984. (Brief yet comprehensive overview from a leading French scholar.)

Peter Rohs, Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Munich: C. H. Beck, 1991. (Brief yet comprehensive overview of Fichte's entire corpus, written in German.)

George Seidel, Fichte's Wissenschaftslehre of 1794: A Commentary on Part I, West Lafayette, IN: Purdue University Press, 1993. (Meant primarily for first-time readers of the Foundations of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre, and thus perhaps the best place to begin in the English secondary literature.)

Internet Resources



 Author Information:

Curtis Bowman
Department of Philosophy
University of Pennsylvania
Logan Hall 433
Philadelphia, PA 19104
USA

The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

© 2001